Newsletter   Secure Checkout   Shopping Cart (0 Items)  
Search:    Welcome Guest! Save up to 30-40% on most items with our awesome everyday discounts!

Philosophy of Geometry from Riemann to Poincaré (Episteme) [Paperback]

By R. Torretti (Author)
Our Price $ 243.46  
Retail Value $ 259.00  
You Save $ 15.54  
Item Number 191388  
Buy New $243.46
Available on the Internet only.

Alternate Formats List Price Our Price Item Number Availability
Hardcover $ 329.00 $ 309.26 191891 In Stock
Paperback $ 259.00 $ 243.46 191388 In Stock

Item description for Philosophy of Geometry from Riemann to Poincaré (Episteme) by R. Torretti...

Philosophy of Geometry from Riemann to Poincar (Episteme) by R. Torretti

Promise Angels is dedicated to bringing you great books at great prices. Whether you read for entertainment, to learn, or for literacy - you will find what you want at!

Item Specifications...

Studio: Springer
Pages   480
Est. Packaging Dimensions:   Length: 9.21" Width: 6.14" Height: 0.96"
Weight:   1.47 lbs.
Binding  Softcover
Release Date   Dec 31, 1984
Publisher   Springer
ISBN  9027718377  
ISBN13  9789027718372  

Availability  55 units.
Availability accurate as of Oct 27, 2016 09:13.
Usually ships within one to two business days from La Vergne, TN.
Orders shipping to an address other than a confirmed Credit Card / Paypal Billing address may incur and additional processing delay.

More About R. Torretti

Register your artisan biography and upload your photo! Are You The Artisan or Author behind this product?
Improve our customers experience by registering for an Artisan Biography Center Homepage.

Product Categories

1Books > Special Features > New & Used Textbooks > Humanities > Philosophy
2Books > Special Features > New & Used Textbooks > Sciences > Mathematics > Geometry
3Books > Special Features > New & Used Textbooks > Sciences > Physics
4Books > Subjects > Nonfiction > Philosophy > General
5Books > Subjects > Professional & Technical > Professional Science > Mathematics > Geometry & Topology > General Geometry
6Books > Subjects > Professional & Technical > Professional Science > Physics > General
7Books > Subjects > Professional & Technical > Professional Science > Physics
8Books > Subjects > Science > General
9Books > Subjects > Science > History & Philosophy > Science
10Books > Subjects > Science > History & Philosophy
11Books > Subjects > Science > Mathematics > Geometry & Topology > General Geometry
12Books > Subjects > Science > Mathematics > Geometry & Topology
13Books > Subjects > Science > Physics > General
14Books > Subjects > Science > Physics

Reviews - What do customers think about Philosophy of Geometry from Riemann to Poincaré (Episteme)?

Extremely prejudiced  Feb 15, 2008
This is an extremely prejudiced history of the foundations of geometry. Torretti is a modernist through and through, incapable of empathy for anyone except Riemann. He goes down the list of contributors to the foundations of geometry, summarises their work haphazardly, translates it into pretentious modern terminology and notation, and proclaims that they were stupid whenever their ideas differ from his own, often imagining himself slaying their entire argument by some trivial observation or other.

An example of the latter phenomena is Helmholtz's discussion of the role of rigid motions in geometry. This Torretti dismisses in two lines, using the analogy of two-dimensional creatures living on a surface. "If they happen to live, say, upon an egg, they will be unable to build transportable rigid figures, and, consequently, according to Helmholtz, they will be incapable of defining a geometry. Though Helmholtz introduces the example of an egg, he does not draw the latter consequence; had he drawn it, it would probably have shocked him out of his operationist bias" (p. 392).

It's the same with Poincaré. "Though Poincaré was well acquainted with Minkowski's work---indeed he even anticipated some of its technical aspects---he apparently failed to appreciate its great significance for the philosophy of geometry" (p. 333), explicitly stating the opposite (p. 414).

These, then, are two instances where Torretti imagines himself to have refuted two of the greatest thinkers in the book by counterexamples that were well known and even discussed by these thinkers themselves. If Torretti was not so quick to dismiss everyone's understanding as inferior to his own, this should perhaps have suggested to him that he had not fully grasped their arguments.

Torretti maintains this condescending attitude throughout. Frege, for example, "shows a lack of understanding ... that is indeed astonishing" (p. 251). Only Riemann is worthy of some praise. Unfortunately, "Riemann's broadminded conception of geometry" was replaced by "Helmholtz's dogma of complete free mobility" (p. 185). Klein, too, in foolishly discussing spaces of constant curvature even though more general spaces can be defined, "loses sight of the full scope of Riemann's conception" (p. 138), and so on.

Unlike Helmholtz, Torretti himself is of course not dogmatic in the least. For example, his is of the balanced opinion that "an axiomatic characterization of projective space would provide the best approach to such a thoroughly unintuitive geometry" (p. 110). Alas, the greatest minds of the century were too stupid to understand that this is the "best" approach; "neither Klein nor his predecessors judged [an axiomatic approach] necessary or even useful" (p. 110), because they were not "aware that their true concern was with abstract structures, not with particular things" (p. 190). Some readers may have been uncomfortable with Torretti's frequent confessions that he "fail[s] to see" (p. 149) the value of so many of the arguments under discussion---indeed, some may wonder why he chose write a book about something he admittedly understands so little about---but now it is all clear. Poor Torretti has to deal with authors who are "not aware" what their "true concern" is. No wonder he does not understand. Of course Torretti knows the "best" way to understand these "true concerns," so his confessions of confusion constitute legitimate criticism.

Now let us look at Torretti's treatment of a specific issue: to what extent Euclidean geometry should be considered an empirical theory. "Paradoxically, the propositions of [geometry do] not seem to be liable to empirical corroboration. Since the times of the Greeks, no geometer had ever thought of subjecting his conclusions to the verdict of experiment." (p. 254). Now this is just ridiculous, even for Torretti. Geometry is plainly the most empirically well-corroborated theory ever created. Torretti, however, in line with his view that the "true concern" of geometry is axiomatics, believes that "Greek mathematicians did not care to determine whether their basic premises were true or not" (p. 9). Torretti then goes on to scorn that proposed proofs of the parallel postulate "depended always explicitly or implicitly upon new assumptions, no less questionable than the postulate itself" (p. 40), and is disappointed that "surprisingly ... no attempt at bringing out every presupposition of Euclid and filling all the gaps in his proofs was carried out in earnest until the end of the 19th century" (p. 189). In other words: Torretti has decided that geometry is about axiomatics and has nothing to do with empiricism, which forces him to look down on every mathematician who ever worked on the parallel postulate and indeed also on everyone else for not doing axiomatics the way he wants. Is there perhaps another way of viewing the history of geometry that does not require us to have contempt for every single mathematician between Euclid and Riemann? Let us assume for the sake of argument that the essence of geometry is not axiomatics but empiricism. First of all, how would Euclid's axioms appear from this point of view? Postulates 1 to 4 are very convincing empirically, even in a finite universe bounded by the sphere of the fixed stars, contrary to Torretti's assertions (pp. 8-9; his main argument in support of his view quoted above); for example, postulate 3 does not require that "every point can be the centre of a circle of any arbitrary radius," but rather that one can construct a circle with a given centre and a given radius (given as in 'from here to here'). The parallel postulate, however, is not empirically convincing. It makes perfect sense, then, that mathematicians should concentrate on the parallel postulate. It is not "surprising" that they did not bother spelling out all of Euclid's assumptions since these are all empirically convincing (e.g., triangle congruencies, etc.). Indeed, from the empirical point of view, work on the parallel postulate was by no means a naive failure leading only to "new assumptions, no less questionable than the postulate itself." Instead, such work was remarkably successful in reducing the empirically intractable parallel postulate to more tangible assumptions. Wallis, for example, derived the parallel postulate from the existence of similar figures, i.e., in effect, from the existence of squares, since "these figure can obviously be multiplied through mere juxtaposition" (p. 45).

Write your own review about Philosophy of Geometry from Riemann to Poincaré (Episteme)

Ask A Question or Provide Feedback regarding Philosophy of Geometry from Riemann to Poincaré (Episteme)

Item Feedback and Product Questions
For immediate assistance call 888.395.0572 during the hours of 10am thru 8pm EST Monday thru Friday and a customer care representative will be happy to help you!

Help us continuously improve our service by reporting your feedback or questions below:

I have a question regarding this product
The information above is incorrect or conflicting
The page has misspellings or incorrect grammar
The page did not load correctly in my browser or created an error.

Email Address:
Anti Spam Question. To combat spammers we require that you answer a simple question.
What color is the sky?
Leave This Blank :
Do Not Change This Text :

Add This Product Widget To Your Website

Looking to add this information to your own website? Then use our Product Widget to allow you to display product information in a frame that is 120 pixels wide by 240 pixels high.

    Copy and paste the following HTML into your website and enjoy!

Order toll-free weekdays 10am thru 10pm EST by phone: 1-888-395-0572 (Lines are closed on holidays & weekends.)
Customer Service | My Account | Track My Orders | Return Policy | Request Free Catalog | Email Newsletter

Gift Certificates
RSS Feeds
About Us
Contact Us
Terms Of Use
Privacy Policy